The Invention of Science: A New History of the Scientific Revolution by David Wootton review a b

Posted by Reinaldo Massengill on Friday, August 30, 2024
This article is more than 8 years oldReview

The Invention of Science: A New History of the Scientific Revolution by David Wootton review – a big bang moment

This article is more than 8 years old

The birth of science in Europe was the greatest revolution of all, argues this dazzling polemic

What is modernity and when did it begin? The answer depends a lot on the nationality and specialism of the historian you ask. Italians favour the achievements of Renaissance art and humanism, as early as the 14th century; northern Europeans opt for the period when cities such as Amsterdam, Paris and London rose to economic and cultural prominence, from the early 16th through to the 18th centuries; some historians of Germany would go as late as 1900. Philosophers are likely to zero in on Descartes in the mid-17th century; economists hold out for the industrial revolution in the late 18th century; political historians push for the American and French revolutions. Beyond Europe, many more periods and places jostle for attention. Everyone has a dog in this fight.

David Wootton’s answer is unequivocal: modernity began with the scientific revolution in Europe, bookended by the dates 1572 (when the Danish astronomer Tycho Brahe identified a new star in the heavens) and 1704 (when Isaac Newton published Opticks). This was “the most important transformation in human history” since the Neolithic era. Later events such as the industrial revolution were no more than the extended consequences of the biggest revolution of them all. Wootton is equally clear about whether the scientific revolution was a matter for celebration (as most Enlightenment thinkers saw it) or regret (as some Romantics felt): it was, in his view, a very good thing indeed.

Compressed into a few sentences, the major theses of this book sound unsurprising. The scientific revolution was not just the motor of modern history, it was the model of modernity. Rational, calculating, advancing at breakneck speed, respecting no authority: science after Newton seemed to embody the power and ever expanding possibilities of a society fixated on the future rather than the past. This is the narrative upon which university professorships and whole departments of the history of science were established after the second world war, and the narrative that a whole generation of historians of science were weaned on.

Yet Wootton believes that historians of what he calls the “post-Kuhn generation” (after the American historian Thomas Kuhn’s influential Structure of Scientific Revolutions, which recast the history of science in the mould of evolution rather than progress) – that is, roughly those who came of age in the 1980s and 90s – have broken with the faith and denied the scientific revolution’s significance as “the big bang” moment of modernity, querying each one of those three words. While they maintain that the understanding of nature was transformed in early modern Europe, recent research on many fronts – anatomy, astronomy, natural history, chemistry, mechanics, physics, medicine, civil and military engineering – has cast doubt on whether these changes constituted a “big bang”.

Wootton’s aim is to offer a new interpretation of what he contends still deserves to be called the scientific revolution. This makes for a big book, with some historiographical chapters (and appendices) that are unlikely to be of interest to readers who are not historians of science over the age of 50. At its core, however, are remarkable essays on the vocabulary of the age of discovery, including terms such as facts, experiments, laws, hypotheses, theories, evidence and judgment. Drawing on a dazzling array of texts, Wootton traces a dawning consciousness that natural knowledge need not be certain to be reliable; that pell-mell experience can be systematised and sharpened by observation and experiment; and that empirical inquiry is of necessity collective.

The great strength of this approach is also its weakness: it is all about texts. If there was one thing the 17th-century proponents of the new philosophy were adamant about, it was that their ways of thinking were about things as well as words. Wootton mentions in passing that improvements in, for example, glass-blowing were a precondition for early experiments on air pressure, and he is alert to how double-entry bookkeeping may have provided a template for other sorts of mathematical abstraction. Yet he underplays how practices such as keeping a commonplace book and achieving high temperatures in a furnace were creatively adapted to new purposes. These connections provide the strongest evidence both for the continuity of new knowledge with old, and for its exuberant originality in hybridising scholarly and practical skills.

Anyone who argues for a sharp and momentous historical discontinuity must come up with causes. Why then? Why there? Wootton’s candidates are plausible enough and chime with older explanations: the role of the printing press in circulating ideas, discoveries and news more widely and quickly; the consequent expansion of a community that could criticise, compete and cooperate in inquiry; the crafting of new methods to probe hidden causes and test hypotheses. But this can’t be the whole story. The printing press, like the internet, spread at least as much misinformation as information; medieval scholars constituted a competitive, critical and cooperative international community; and if, by around 1730, educated Europeans had put aside their belief in witches, it wasn’t because science had decided the question.

Wootton is committed to making the scientific revolution both discontinuous with all that came before and continuous with all that followed. This leads him to make some odd claims: for example, that the empirical inquiries of Aristotle into organic life or the physico-mathematical achievements of Archimedes were of qualitatively different sort from those of early modern and modern naturalists, despite the countervailing testimony of the likes of Galileo and Georges Cuvier, who recognised kindred spirits across the centuries. Still more curious is Wootton’s insistence that the tracks for modern science were laid down in the 17th century and that it has simply been chugging along ever since. The extravagant fertility of science suggests otherwise. Since 1704 it has produced not only new discoveries and theories, but also new ways of knowing. Today’s computer simulations, for example, are as novel a transformation of scientific experience as experiments were in the 17th century. Science was not invented once, but over and over again: the model not only of progress, but work in progress.

Lorraine Daston is director of the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science in Berlin. To order The Invention of Science for £24 (RRP £30), go to bookshop.theguardian.com or call 0330 333 6846. Free UK p&p over £10, online orders only. Phone orders min. p&p of £1.99.

Explore more on these topicsShareReuse this content

ncG1vNJzZmivp6x7tbTEoKyaqpSerq96wqikaJqfpLi0e5FpaG5nnqTDcH6XaKCnrpWjwaq7zWamn2WjmLamusKeZKybmZq7tbXFoppmqpWrvK3B06Kmp2WUlsOqsIywpqispKS7br7Er6Cerw%3D%3D